Results for 'Paul Wilhelm K. Maximilian Runze'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Grit.Sarah K. Paul & Jennifer M. Morton - 2018 - Ethics 129 (2):175-203.
    Many of our most important goals require months or even years of effort to achieve, and some never get achieved at all. As social psychologists have lately emphasized, success in pursuing such goals requires the capacity for perseverance, or "grit." Philosophers have had little to say about grit, however, insofar as it differs from more familiar notions of willpower or continence. This leaves us ill-equipped to assess the social and moral implications of promoting grit. We propose that grit has an (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  2. Believing in Others.Sarah K. Paul & Jennifer M. Morton - 2018 - Philosophical Topics 46 (1):75-95.
    Suppose some person 'A' sets out to accomplish a difficult, long-term goal such as writing a passable Ph.D. thesis. What should you believe about whether A will succeed? The default answer is that you should believe whatever the total accessible evidence concerning A's abilities, circumstances, capacity for self-discipline, and so forth supports. But could it be that what you should believe depends in part on the relationship you have with A? We argue that it does, in the case where A (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  3. Plan B.Sarah K. Paul - 2022 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 100 (3):550-564.
    We sometimes strive to achieve difficult goals when our evidence suggests that success is unlikely – not just because it will require strength of will, but because we are targets of prejudice and discrimination or because success will require unusual ability. Optimism about one’s prospects can be useful for persevering in these cases. That said, excessive optimism can be dangerous; when our evidence is unfavourable, we should be at most agnostic about whether we will succeed. This paper explores the nature (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  4. How We Know What We're Doing.Sarah K. Paul - 2009 - Philosophers' Imprint 9:1-24.
    G.E.M. Anscombe famously claimed that acting intentionally entails knowing "without observation" what one is doing. Among those that have taken her claim seriously, an influential response has been to suppose that in order to explain this fact, we should conclude that intentions are a species of belief. This paper argues that there are good reasons to reject this "cognitivist" view of intention in favor of the view that intentions are distinctively practical attitudes that are not beliefs and do not constitutively (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  5. Doxastic Self-Control.Sarah K. Paul - 2015 - American Philosophical Quarterly 52 (2):145-58.
    This paper discusses the possibility of autonomy in our epistemic lives, and the importance of the concept of the first person in weathering fluctuations in our epistemic perspective over time.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  6. II—What Should ‘Impostor Syndrome’ Be?Sarah K. Paul - 2019 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 93 (1):227-245.
    In her thought-provoking symposium contribution, ‘What Is Impostor Syndrome?’, Katherine Hawley fleshes out our everyday understanding of that concept. This response builds on Hawley’s account to ask the ameliorative question of whether the everyday concept best serves the normative goals of promoting social justice and enhancing well-being. I raise some sceptical worries about the usefulness of the notion, in so far as it is centred on doxastic attitudes that include doubt about one’s own talent or skill. I propose instead that (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  7. The conclusion of practical reasoning: the shadow between idea and act.Sarah K. Paul - 2013 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 43 (3):287-302.
    There is a puzzle about how to understand the conclusion of a successful instance of practical reasoning. Do the considerations adduced in reasoning rationalize the particular doing of an action, as Aristotle is sometimes interpreted as claiming? Or does reasoning conclude in the formation of an attitude – an intention, say – that has an action-type as its content? This paper attempts to clarify what is at stake in that debate and defends the latter view against some of its critics.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  8. How we know what we intend.Sarah K. Paul - 2012 - Philosophical Studies 161 (2):327-346.
    How do we know what our intentions are? It is argued that work on self-knowledge has tended to neglect the attitude of intention, and that an epistemological account is needed that is attuned to the specific features of that state. Richard Moran’s Authorship view, on which we can acquire self-knowledge by making up our minds, offers a promising insight for such an account: we do not normally discover what we intend through introspection. However, his formulation of the Authorship view, developed (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  9.  11
    Über Intensionen und Modalitäten.Wilhelm K. Essler - 1970 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 11 (4):416-424.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10. Intention, belief, and wishful thinking: Setiya on “practical knowledge”.Sarah K. Paul - 2009 - Ethics 119 (3):546-557.
  11. Deviant Formal Causation.Sarah K. Paul - 2011 - Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 5 (3):1-24.
    What is the role of practical thought in determining the intentional action that is performed? Donald Davidson’s influential answer to this question is that thought plays an efficient-causal role: intentional actions are those events that have the correct causal pedigree in the agent's beliefs and desires. But the Causal Theory of Action has always been plagued with the problem of “deviant causal chains,” in which the right action is caused by the right mental state but in the wrong way. This (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  12.  4
    Ein nichtkonstruktiver Beweis des ersten $\varepsilon$-theorems.Wilhelm K. Essler - 1970 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 11 (3):369-371.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  13. Diachronic Incontinence is a Problem in Moral Philosophy.Sarah K. Paul - 2014 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 57 (3):337-355.
    Is there a rational requirement enjoining continence over time in the intentions one has formed, such that anyone going in for a certain form of agency has standing reason to conform to such a requirement? This paper suggests that there is not. I argue that Michael Bratman’s defense of such a requirement succeeds in showing that many agents have a reason favoring default intention continence much of the time, but does not establish that all planning agents have such a reason (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  14.  54
    Some ways of operationally introducing dispositional predicates with regard to scientific and ordinary practice.Wilhelm K. Essler & Rainer Trapp - 1977 - Synthese 34 (4):371 - 396.
  15.  3
    Geist und Macht: Versuche einer Entschleierung des deutschen "Idealismus".Paul Wilhelm Wenger - 1948 - Augsburg: J.W. Naumann.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. The Transparency of Mind.Sarah K. Paul - 2014 - Philosophy Compass 9 (5):295-303.
    In philosophical inquiry into the mind, the metaphor of ‘transparency’ has been attractive to many who are otherwise in deep disagreement. It has thereby come to have a variety of different and mutually incompatible connotations. The mind is said to be transparent to itself, our perceptual experiences are said to be transparent to the world, and our beliefs are said to be transparent to – a great many different things. The first goal of this essay is to sort out the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  17. The courage of conviction.Sarah K. Paul - 2015 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 45 (5-6):1-23.
    Is there a sense in which we exercise direct volitional control over our beliefs? Most agree that there is not, but discussions tend to focus on control in forming a belief. The focus here is on sustaining a belief over time in the face of ‘epistemic temptation’ to abandon it. It is argued that we do have a capacity for ‘doxastic self-control’ over time that is partly volitional in nature, and that its exercise is rationally permissible.
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  18. The transparency of intention.Sarah K. Paul - 2015 - Philosophical Studies 172 (6):1529-1548.
    The attitude of intention is not usually the primary focus in philosophical work on self-knowledge. A recent exception is the so-called “Transparency” theory of self-knowledge, which attempts to explain how we know our own minds by appeal to reflection on non-mental facts. Transparency theories are attractive in light of their relative psychological economy compared to views that must posit a dedicated mechanism of ‘inner sense’. However, it is argued here, focusing on proposals by Richard Moran and Alex Byrne, that the (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  19. Of Reasons and Recognition.Sarah K. Paul & Jennifer M. Morton - 2014 - Analysis 74 (2):339-348.
  20.  16
    Die Kreativität Der Bilateralen Reduktionssätze.Wilhelm K. Essler - 1975 - Erkenntnis 9 (3):383 - 392.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  21. Willing, Wanting, Waiting, by Richard Holton.Sarah K. Paul - 2011 - Mind 120 (479):889-892.
  22.  1
    Some Remarks Concerning Partial Definitions in Empirical Sciences.Wilhelm K. Essler - 1980 - Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 61 (4):455-462.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23. Good Intentions and the Road to Hell.Sarah K. Paul - 2017 - Philosophical Explorations 20 (2):40-54.
    G.E.M. Anscombe famously remarked that an adequate philosophy of psychology was needed before we could do ethics. Fifty years have passed, and we should now ask what significance our best theories of the psychology of agency have for moral philosophy. My focus is on non-moral conceptions of autonomy and self-governance that emphasize the limits of deliberation -- the way in which one's cares render certain options unthinkable, one's intentions and policies filter out what is inconsistent with them, and one's resolutions (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24.  9
    Métaphysische Anfangsgründe der Mechanik.Joachim Labude Wilhelm K. Essler - 1999 - Dialectica 53 (3-4):307-344.
    Zusammenfassung:Ausgehend von der philosophischen Grundhaltung Kants, dass jedes System von empiri‐schen Urteilen – jede empirische Theorie – seine epistemologische Grundlage in einem System von synthetischen Sätzen, die hierfür apriorisch akzeptiert werden, hat, wird eine Axiomatisierung der Mechanik bis hin zum Impulsbegriff nach H. Hermes dargestellt. Dieses System von Axiomen veyendet als Grundbegriffe lediglich den der reellen Zahlen, den des Bezugssystem, der den Übergang zum mathematischen Raum ermöglicht, und den der Genidentität, der das stetige Fortschreiten von Materiepunkten beschreibt.Das System von Hermes (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  29
    Am anfang war die tat.Wilhelm K. Essler - 1996 - Erkenntnis 44 (3):257 - 277.
    First, the paper argues that Tarski's theory of language levels is best understood not only as a method for avoiding semantic paradoxes by rigidly restricting the expressive power of a language, but as a natural expression of an epistemological process of reflection which is more adequately understood as a process and not by its result. Second, it is argued that the apparent philosophical controversy between materialism and idealism dissolves whithin this process of reflection. If one has raised above the lowest (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  38
    A note on functional explanation.Wilhelm K. Essler - 1978 - Erkenntnis 13 (1):371 - 376.
  27. » Über die Interpretation von Wissenschaftssprachen «.Wilhelm K. Essler - 1970 - Philosophisches Jahrbuch 77 (1):117-30.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  28.  9
    Über die Voraussetzungen der Erfahrungserkenntnis aus der Sicht des Operationalismus.Wilhelm K. Essler - 2004 - Kriterion - Journal of Philosophy 18 (1):32-38.
    It is shown that-at least in contemporary physics-the single measuring results are completely irrelevant w.r.t. testing a metric law. As a consequence, laws are neither gained by induction nor rejected by falsification. Even statistical generalizations of measuring values, when-in the sense of some philosophers-falsifying laws are not always regarded as falsifying instances by physicists.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29. Über die Voraussetzungen der Erfahrungserkenntnis aus der Sicht des Operationalismus.Wilhelm K. Essler - 2004 - Kriterion - Journal of Philosophy 1 (18):32-38.
    It is shown that-at least in contemporary physics-the single measuring results are completely irrelevant w.r.t. testing a metric law. As a consequence, laws are neither gained by induction nor rejected by falsification. Even statistical generalizations of measuring values, when-in the sense of some philosophers-falsifying laws are not always regarded as falsifying instances by physicists.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  30.  35
    Corrupted concepts and empiricism.Wilhelm K. Essler - 1978 - Erkenntnis 12 (2):181 - 187.
  31.  14
    Corrupted Concepts and Empiricism. The Philosophical Relevance of the Goodman Paradox.Wilhelm K. Essler - 1978 - Erkenntnis 12 (2):181 - 187.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  32. Die Philosophie des Buddhismus.Wilhelm K. Essler & Ulrich Mamat - 2007 - Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 69 (3):614-614.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  33.  14
    Editorial.Wilhelm K. Essler & Wolfgang Spohn - 1997 - Erkenntnis 47 (3):1-3.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  10
    Einführung in die Logik.Wilhelm K. Essler - 1980 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 45 (2):381-382.
  35.  14
    Editorial note.Wilhelm K. Essler - 1988 - Erkenntnis 28 (3):295-296.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  42
    Fundamentals of a Semi-Kantian Metaphysics of Knowledge.Wilhelm K. Essler - 1982 - The Monist 65 (1):106-115.
    It was 250 years ago that Immanuel Kant’s “Kritik der reinen Vernunft” was published first. Generations of philosophers regarded this work as the ne plus ultra in epistemology or metaphysics of knowledge. Since central parts of his doctrine can, to say the least, be considered to be incompatible with fundamentals in current physical theorizing, many philosophers have continued to explore his ideas. Some of them do so believing that Kant’s convictions have definitely been proved to be true and that therefore (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. Grundzüge der Logik 11. Klassen. Relationen. Zahlen.Wilhelm K. Essler, Elke Brendel & Rosa F. Martínez Cruzado - 1990 - Erkenntnis 32 (2):283-291.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Gründzüge der Logik, Teil I: Das Logische Schließen.Wilhelm K. Essler & Rosa F. Martinez Cruzado - 1987 - Erkenntnis 26 (2):301-304.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  39.  24
    Gorgias hat Recht!Wilhelm K. Essler - 1993 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 44 (1):265-292.
    Die Platonische Position des mengentheoretischen Universalismus, nach der das Mengenuniversum sprachunabhängig existiert, durch reine Anschauung erkannt und sprachlich mitteilbar ist, kann aus folgenden Gründen nicht aufrechterhalten werden: Die metalogischen Ergebnisse von Skolem und Löwenheim zeigen, daß die von einem Platonisten verwendete Sprache der engeren Quantorenlogik NichtStandard-Modelle besitzt, so daß er daher insbesondere nicht mitteilen kann, was er mit,Allklasse',,leere Klasse' und,Element' meint, da es nicht intendierte Interpretationen für diese Ausdrücke gibt. Hieraus folgt, daß der Zermelosche Mengentrichter, den der Platonist als durch (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40.  5
    Gorgias hat Recht!Wilhelm K. Essler - 1993 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 44 (1):265-292.
    Die Platonische Position des mengentheoretischen Universalismus, nach der das Mengenuniversum sprachunabhängig existiert, durch reine Anschauung erkannt und sprachlich mitteilbar ist, kann aus folgenden Gründen nicht aufrechterhalten werden: Die metalogischen Ergebnisse von Skolem und Löwenheim zeigen, daß die von einem Platonisten verwendete Sprache der engeren Quantorenlogik NichtStandard-Modelle besitzt, so daß er daher insbesondere nicht mitteilen kann, was er mit,Allklasse',,leere Klasse' und,Element' meint, da es nicht intendierte Interpretationen für diese Ausdrücke gibt. Hieraus folgt, daß der Zermelosche Mengentrichter, den der Platonist als durch (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  1
    Kant und kein Ende.Wilhelm K. Essler - 1991 - Dialectica 45 (2‐3):133-163.
    ZusammenfassungAusgehend von einer operational vorgehenden Wissenschaftstheorie, die die kantische Ein‐teilung der erfahrungswissenschaftlichen Urteile auf den heutigen Stand dieser philosophischen Disziplin überträgt, wird eine Epistemologie entwickelt, welche sich sowohl an den Ergebnissen der Metalogik und philosophischen Semantik als auch an den empirischen Hypothesen der gegen‐wärtigen Wahrnehmungspsychologie orientiert. In bezug auf den Inhalt des zugrundegelegten Universums der zu interpretierenden Sprache wird hierbei eine Position des Suppositionismus vertreten, welche von einem sprachabhängigen Erkennen der Objekte ausgeht, deren Existenz somit nur vorausgesetzt werden kann. Bezüglich (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42.  18
    Métaphysische Anfangsgründe der Mechanik.Wilhelm K. Essler, Joachim Labude & Stefanie Ucsnay - 1999 - Dialectica 53 (3‐4):307-344.
  43.  6
    Metaphysical bases of mechanics.Wilhelm K. Essler, Joachim Labude & Stefanie Ucsnay - 1999 - Dialectica 53 (3-4):307-344.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  44.  1
    On Solidity and Rigidity.Wilhelm K. Essler - 2013 - In Michael Frauchiger (ed.), Reference, Rationality, and Phenomenology: Themes from Føllesdal. De Gruyter. pp. 123-136.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45.  4
    On Using Measuring Numbers according to Measuring Theories.Wilhelm K. Essler - 2008 - ProtoSociology 25:49-65.
    It was shown by Frege that four of the five axioms of Peano can be regarded as analytical truths; and it was shown by Russell that the remaining axiom cannot be regarded as being analytically true or even as being analytically false, that this axiom thus is to be regarded as a synthetic statement. In using the concept of apriority in the sense of Reichenbach, it can be shown that this synthetic axiom is to be regarded as an apriorical truth (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  46.  2
    On Using Measuring Numbers according to Measuring Theories.Wilhelm K. Essler - 2008 - In Gerhard Preyer (ed.), Philosophy of Mathematics: Set Theory, Measuring Theories, and Nominalism. Frankfort, Germany: Ontos. pp. 53-70.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  17
    Persönliche anmerkungen.Wilhelm K. Essler - 1983 - Erkenntnis 19 (1-3):417 - 422.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  48.  31
    Piron's approach to the foundations of quantum mechanics.Wilhelm K. Essler & Gerhard Zoubek - 1981 - Erkenntnis 16 (3):411 - 418.
  49.  15
    Sprache und Konvention.Wilhelm K. Essler - 1987 - Dialectica 41 (1‐2):97-116.
    ZusammenfassungOhne Zweifel stehen Sprachen und Konventionen in engen Beziehungen zueinander; grosse Teile der Oberflächenstrukturen unserer natürlichen Sprachen hängen von Konventionen ab, und um aussersprachliches Verhalten durch Konventionen zu regeln, benötigt man eine gemeinsame Sprache. Zu fragen ist dann, ob eine reale oder idealisierte Gemeinschaft von Personen sich eine gemeinsame Sprache durch irgendeine Art von Konvention erstmals schaffen kann, ohne dabei bereits ausdrücklich oder stillschweigend eine gemeinsame Sprache zu benützen, die nicht weniger ausdrücksreich als die zu kreierende ist. Es wird gezeigt, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  50.  4
    Truth and Knowledge.Wilhelm K. Essler - 1998 - ProtoSociology 12:12-39.
1 — 50 / 1000